2. Touch of Evil
We started, in the previous module, with the question of
how law understands and frames the object of its enquiry. This is
especially complicated when this object is as complex as what I am
calling the practice of cinema.
It is now time to push that enquiry a little further. Let us look at
one of the constantly recurring themes in any discussion of cinema.
• Exercise
Try this small exercise. Conduct a discussion. Just ask a
few people whether they think that cinema should be treated on a
different footing (for instance with regard to censorship issues) than,
say, literature or painting. If they do think that cinema should be
treated differently, then why? Make a note of all the common points that
emerge.
In this module, we shall be looking at most of the common points
that inevitably emerge in any such discussion. We will show how cinema
gets to be perceived by the law, and what are the assumptions that the
law makes about the nature and impact of cinema, and we will also where
these ideas come from.
• CINEMA AND "EVIL"
One of the words, repeated over and over again in debates
on cinema and its impact, is the word ‘Evil’. ‘Evil’ is perhaps the most
used phrase in the vocabulary of the regulation of cinema. A quick
survey, both of popular discourse as well as juridical discourse quickly
reveals the ease with which cinema is narrated in terms of evil: the
evil influences of cinema, the capacity of film for evil, the evil that
it is doing etc. Evil also emerges as the primary justification for why
the cinema is seen to need a different kind of regulation than the
other arts.
Is there a difference in the way that the word evil is invoked in
cinema, as against other modes of expressive speech such as literature?
Is "evil" used in the cinema as just another descriptive word that has
slipped into common parlance, reduced into a thoughtless cliché? Or is
the invocation of the idea more than a mere coincidence? Can there be
fascinating history to this use, and can that history have consequences
for how we might understand even contemporary debates on film
censorship?
A very respected film historian, Tom Gunning, says that there is a
critical difference between literature and cinema here: unlike
literature, the question arises for the cinema, as to whether it is
inherently evil. That there is something intrinsic to the medium itself,
not merely to a class of films which could be said to embody evil. So
“evil", says Gunning, is something that literature expresses; it is not
inherent in the very signifiers of the text, the materiality and
perceptual qualities of literature. But with cinema...doubts arise about
its innocence from its origin”
• Questions for discussion
1. Discuss this difference that Gunning is making between
literature’s capacity to represent evil, and cinema’s capacity for evil.
2. Gunning says that evil in not something inherent to the very
signifiers of the text. By implication, can it be understood that there
are some inherent qualities of the technology of film that makes it a
candidate for evil? Return to the notes that you have made from your
discussion on the qualities of cinema, and see if any of them make
cinema a candidate for the category of being evil in it.
• A GENEALOGY FOR EVIL?
We shall now try to reconstruct a genealogy of evil in
relation to cinema. We shall do this by tracing backwards the history of
HOW notions of evil has always inflicted legal accounts of cinema, in
India and internationally. We need to begin by looking at the various
milestones of evil in law’s response to cinema.
In the history of censorship in India, one of the most significant
landmarks is a Supreme Court case, K.A. Abbas v. Union of India. For the
full text of the famous Abbas judgement, click here
K.A. Abbas was a very famous film maker who is also famous for
having directed Amitabh Bachan’s debut film, Saat Hindustani (A remake
of Akira Kurosawa’s Seven Samurai). Abbas saw himself as a very
"realistic" filmmaker who wanted to use cinema for social
transformation. He was also a member of the Khosla Committee on Film
Censorship that was set up by the Government of India (which we shall
discuss later). In the course of its working, Abbas got into a quarrel
with another member who ridiculed filmmakers in India saying that none
of the films they made could even qualify for political censorship.
Abbas then made a film A Tale of Four Cities with the express intention
of challenging the constitutional validity of pre-censorship of cinema
in India.
Note:
The difference between pre-censorship and censorship: Where you need
permission before you can even circulate any material it is
pre-censorship (e.g. a film cannot be shown without censor certificate;
on the other hand, after the circulation of some material, if it found
to be offensive, action can be taken against it and the circulation can
be stopped; e.g. a book which is found to be obscene)
• Why Abbas is Important
The significance of the K.A. Abbas case is primariloy
this. After he won his legal case for saving A Tale of Four Cities from
being censored, he amended his petition to raise a larger constitutional
challenge; he said that pre-censorship for cinema was in violation of
Art. 19(1)(a): that it was against the fundamental right of freedom of
speech and expression. The case therefore dealt with the question of
cinema as an institution itself, and went beyond any specific film, and
it still remains the leading judgment pronounced by the Supreme Court on
the question. The Court upholding the differential treatment afforded
to cinema has necessarily to construct an argument of difference as
well.
In the Abbas judgement, Justice Hidayatullah stated:
“Further it has been almost universally recognized that the
treatment of motion pictures must be different from that of other forms
of art and expression. This arises from the instant appeal of the motion
picture, its versatility, realism (often surrealism), and its
co-ordination of the visual and aural senses. The art of the cameraman,
with trick photography, vista vision and three-dimensional
representation thrown in, has made the cinema picture more true to life
than even the theatre or indeed any other form of representative art.
The motion picture is able to stir up emotions more deeply than any
other product of art. Its effect particularly on children and
adolescents is very great since their immaturity makes them more
willingly suspend their disbelief than mature men and women. They also
remember the action in the picture and try to emulate or imitate what
they have seen. Therefore classification of films into two categories of
"U" films and "A" films is a reasonable classification. It is also for
this reason that motion pictures must be regarded differently from other
forms of speech and expression. A person reading a book or other
writing nor hearing a speech or viewing a painting or sculpture is not
so deeply stirred as by seeing a motion picture. Therefore the treatment
of the latter on a different footing is also a valid classification”
1. What, according to the judgment, are the essential
qualities that distinguish cinema from any other form? How do these
compare with the discussion that you have conducted on the qualities of
cinema? Are there are any similarities? If there are not, then is it
because cinema is no longer an object or technology of "mystery and
astonishment", the way that it used to be?
2. The judge seems to be saying that the problem of cinema arises
not so much from its inability, as it were, to represent reality, as
much as the fact that it is precisely able to do it too effectively.
What do you make of this statement?
3. Finally, the judgment seems to rely heavily on the idea that that
cinema has the ability to impact differential classes of people,
especially children who are prone to believe whatever is happening, who
cannot distinguish between the illusion on the screen and reality. Would
you agree or disagree with this statement. Elaborate.
Hidayatullah's paragraph has more or less become the
cornerstone for the way in which the law deals with cinema, and is
quoted in almost every successive case related to the Cinematograph act
in India.
Of course it did not help Abbas’s case that he himself had written
in a similar way on the nature of cinema, and the court in this case
gleefully quoted Abbas himself to buttress their argument. They cited
Abbas’s argument “even if we believe that a novelist or a painter or a
musician should be free to write, paint and compose music without the
interference of the State machinery, I doubt if anyone will advocate the
same freedom to be extended to the commercial exploitation of a
powerful medium of expression and entertainment like the cinema. One can
imagine the results if an unbridled commercial cinema is allowed to
cater to the lowest common denominator of popular taste, specially in a
country which, after two centuries of political and cultural domination,
is still suffering from a confusion and debasement of cultural values.
Freedom of expression cannot, and should not, be interpreted as a
license for the cinemagnates to make money by pandering to, and thereby
propagating, shoddy and vulgar taste."
• Where does the Court get its Ideas?
Document Actions